Copyright 2001 eMediaMillWorks, Inc.
(f/k/a Federal
Document Clearing House, Inc.)
Federal Document Clearing House
Congressional Testimony
July 19, 2001, Thursday
SECTION: CAPITOL HILL HEARING TESTIMONY
LENGTH: 4110 words
COMMITTEE:
HOUSE JUDICIARY
SUBCOMMITTEE: CRIME
HEADLINE: CLONING PROHIBITION BODY ARMOR
RESTRICTIONS(MARKUP)
TESTIMONY-BY: GERARD V. BRADLEY,
PROFESSOR OF LAW
AFFILIATION: UNIVERSITY OF NOTRE DAME
BODY: U.S. House of Representatives
Committee on the Judiciary, Subcommittee on Crime
Hearings on
Human Cloning H.R. 1644, H.R. (Greenwood)
June 19, 2001
Testimony of Gerard V. Bradley
Professor of Law, University of
Notre Dame
Mr. Chairman and members of the Subcommittee. I am grateful
for this opportunity to evaluate the proposed anti-cloning bills, both from a
constitutional viewpoint and from the viewpoint of criminal law and its
enforcement. A copy of my entire C.V. is attached to the written testimony. I
should like to note, however, that I have taught, and published widely, in the
areas of constitutional law and criminal procedure throughout my eighteen years
as a professor. Before that, I was a prosecutor in New York City, serving as an
Assistant to Robert Morgenthau, District Attorney of New York County. I shall
focus principally on H.R. 1644, and especially on its constitutionality. My
judgment is that this bill is a proper exercise of Congress's power over
interstate commerce, and that it is entirely consistent with relevant
constitutional doctrines, particularly those protecting privacy and reproductive
freedom. The Greenwood bill is also a legitimate exercise of Congress's
interstate commerce power. But it raises serious constitutional questions which
H.R. 1644 does not. Moreover, the Greenwood "prohibition" is unenforceable:
practically speaking, the bill will not attain its stated objective of banning
cloning intended to initiate a pregnancy. My judgment is this: the only
effective way to prohibit human reproductive cloning is to prohibit all
human cloning, as H.R.1644 does. And H.R. 1644 provides the
route to that end free of constitutional difficulty.
The
Constitutionality of H.R. 1644
The first question about H.R. 1644, as
with every act of Congress, is whether a specific constitutional authorization
supports the proposed exercise of Congressional power. This bill identifies the
Commerce Clause as Congress's lawmaking authority. The controlling Commerce
Clause precedents are summarized in U.S. v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995). Lopez
supplies the criteria for my analysis.
On one view of H.R. 1644, there
cannot be any question concerning the Commerce Clause. The bill states that it
"shall be unlawful for any person or entity, public or private, in or affecting
interstate commerce" to engage in any of the prohibited acts. It is possible to
read the jurisdictional (i.e., interstate commerce) language here as
constituting an element of the offense. On this reading, a successful
prosecution under the act would require proof either that the particular
defendant's activities (in general) affected interstate commerce, or that the
charged act(s) of cloning did. In other words, no one could be convicted under
the proposed act without proof of the requisite effect upon interstate commerce.
Where that proof failed, the prohibition could not attach. On this view of the
bill, no facial attack on commerce clause grounds is possible.
I mention
this reading not because I think it is the one intended by the bill's drafters.
H.R. 1644 intends, it rather seems to me, a flat prohibition of
human
cloning, as an exercise of Congressional power over interstate
commerce. I turn to the constitutionality of that momentarily. I mention this
alternative reading to support the following caveat: if a court down the line,
reviewing an enforcement action under the enacted bill, doubts the
constitutionality of a flat prohibition, that court will not hold the bill
unconstitutional. Instead, that doubting court will adopt the narrower, and
safer, reading I just described. Again: there is almost no chance that this bill
will be held unconstitutional on Commerce Clause grounds by any court. There is,
however, some chance that a court will adopt the safer reading of the
jurisdictional language.
Let us henceforth treat H.R. 1644 as a flat
prohibition of
human cloning. My judgment is that, even with
the modest pruning of Congressional commerce authority in recent Supreme Court
cases, the bill is constitutional.
First, there is no doubt that
Congress may regulate interstate commerce for non-commercial purposes. Congress
may go so far as to prohibit certain activities, in or affecting interstate
commerce, solely because they are deemed immoral, injurious to human dignity, or
violative of human rights. Many cases support this proposition. The most
compelling may be those upholding the Civil Rights Act of 1964, specifically,
its ban on racial discrimination in motels and restaurants serving (in even
minuscule part) interstate travelers. See Katzenbach v. McClung, 379 U.S. 294
(1964); Heart of Atlanta Motel v. United States, 379 U.S. 241 (1964).
H.R. 1644 prohibits
human cloning for a number of
reasons, recited in the "Findings" section. That most, or even all, may be
non-commercial therefore raises no interesting constitutional question.
Does a flat prohibition on
human cloning have the
requisite connection to interstate commerce? The prevailing Supreme Court tests,
as found in the Lopez majority opinion, recognize plenary Congressional power
over the instrumentalities of interstate commerce, a protective power extending
to intrastate activities which threaten the instrumentalities of interstate
commerce. Most of the activity prohibited by H.R. 1644 -- "ship [ping]" or
"receiv[ing]" products of
human cloning, for example -- could
be supported by these twin powers. Congress could, without constitutional
question, flatly prohibit all use of the mail and wires in furtherance of
human cloning, prohibit all entities receiving any federal
funds from
human cloning, and even utilize its special maritime
and admiralty jurisdiction in aid of a total ban.
My judgment is,
however, that these powers, either alone or in tandem, may not be sufficient to
support all that is banned by the bill. My opinion is that some portion of the
flat ban on
human cloning must rely upon the third type of
Congressional commerce power, that over intrastate activity affecting interstate
commerce.
The Lopez court emphasized, over against some prior authority,
that the test was whether the regulated activity "substantially" affects
interstate commerce. H.R. 1644 does not use the modifier "substantial". But that
alone does not affect the bill's constitutionality, so long as it can be shown,
in a later judicial test, that a "substantial" effect exists. Does Congress have
a reasonable basis for asserting that "substantial" effect? I surely believe so.
Here is the argument that Congress does. It is important at the outset
to exactly identify the activity whose relation to interstate commerce is in
question. That activity is not somatic cell nuclear transfer, the scientific act
prohibited by H.R. 1644. For that prohibition is merely the means chosen by
Congress to forestall a different, much more substantial economic activity: the
whole prospective set of activities in connection with human reproductive
cloning, and with cloning for more limited scientific, medical, academic
purposes -- which would arise in due course absent H.R. 1644.
This
projected web of activities would be high tech; it would be dependent upon the
interstate transportation of raw materials, lab equipment, and products; and it
would rely upon the national and international communication of needs, research
results, and opportunities. Though precisely speaking not a commodity for sale,
cloned human embryos could reasonably be projected to becomes articles of
exchange, traded for "service" fees. In short, Congress could reasonably
conclude that H.R. 1644 is a pre- emptive strike against a potentially enormous
interstate traffic in connection with
human cloning.
The central aim of H.R. 1644 is to forestall this projected
commodification of the results of
human cloning. Nothing in the
Constitution or the case law requires Congress to wait and see how things play
out before acting. That Congress is poised to act pre-emptively against an evil
is neither unusual nor constitutionally troublesome. True, if the bill succeeds
in its goals, we will never know in fine what the unregulated market in
human cloning would have looked like. But that fact weighs in
favor of constitutionality. For to strike down the bill as unconstitutional, a
reviewing court would have to overrule, without any contrary facts in hand,
Congress's informed judgment about the future.
In my professional
opinion, there is little chance that a court, reviewing a factual basis like the
one just described, will upset, as an unwarranted exercise of the interstate
commerce power, Congress's judgment to prohibit
human cloning,
The Privacy Cases
According to the Supreme Court, its privacy
cases have established constitutional protection for the right: to marry; to
have children; to direct the education and upbringing of one's children; to
marital privacy; to use contraception; to bodily integrity; and to abortion. See
Washington v. Glucksberg, 117 S.Ct. 2258, 2267 (1997) (citations omitted). Only
two of these rights are in the neighborhood of cloning. For the proposition in
favor of a right to "have children", the Court relied upon a 1942 decision
against involuntary sterilization. For the right to "marital privacy" the Court
cited Griswold, its 1965 decision in favor a right of married couples to use
contraception. There is therefore no Supreme Court authority nearly in line
against a ban on
human cloning. There is, generally,
Supreme Court precedent in favor of a woman's right to decide, by herself,
whether to "bear or beget" a child. But the cases giving rise to that right make
clear that "begotten" is surely not made -- or cloned. And "bear" unequivocally
refers to the abortion liberty. There is also authority for the proposition
that, in no exact sense, one has a right not to be a become a parent against
one's wishes. But that right is limited to pregnant women; a man either deceived
or the victim of contraceptive failure has no constitutional traction whatsoever
upon the decision of the woman to abort their child, or to carry their child to
term. Besides, this woman's right is surely asymmetrical. A right not to be a
parent does not imply or entail a right, simply, to be a parent.
No
case, in any court, has ever held in favor of a constitutional right to
reproduction by cloning. In fact, no case has ever held that anyone has a right
to reproduce by in vitro fertilization (IVF).
To generate a "privacy"
argument against H.R. 1644 one would have to go beyond all prior holdings of all
the courts. The only way that I can think of to make that argument would detach
a commodious phrase, such as the "right to have children", from its
jurisprudential moorings, and then (somehow) maintain that the broad concept
implies a right to reproduce by cloning. But no such argument could possibly
succeed, as I understand the Supreme Court's stance towards all such novel
claims of constitutional rights.
The Court has repeatedly emphasized two
fundamental requirements for any "privacy" argument in favor of an unrecognized
liberty interest. First, the asserted liberty must be, objectively speaking,
"deeply rooted in this nation's history and tradition". See Glucksberg at 2268.
Cloning clearly does not satisfy this requirement. Not only is it an entirely
new technology. By reducing reproduction to asexual replication, it is radically
unlike all rights sounding in "reproductive liberty" heretofore recognized. In
other words, even argument by analogy will not work for cloning.
Second,
the Supreme Court has cautioned, in very strong terms, against arguments relying
upon spacious phrasing. The Court has insisted that the asserted liberty be
described in specific, concrete terms. Vague, open-ended generalities will not
do. For example, the Court has rejected characterizations of its Cruzan holding
as favoring a "right to die". Instead, the Court, in its own description, held
for a "constitutionally protected right to refuse lifesaving hydration and
nutrition". Nor was Glucksberg itself, according to the Court, about a "right to
die" or a "right to commit suicide". It was instead about "a right to commit
suicide which itself includes a right to assistance in doing so." Id.
According to this second requirement, no general "right to reproduce",
"to be a parent", or "to have a child" will be credited, either as a conclusion
or as a premise, in any argument in the Supreme Court. The Court will insist
that a claimant defend a right specifically to cloning. Given the high burden of
persuasion imposed by the high Court upon such claimants, the chances of success
in the are virtually nil.
The Supreme Court has said: "We must therefore
'exercise the utmost care whenever we are asked to break new ground in this
field'...lest the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause be subtly
transformed into the policy preferences of the members of this Court". Id. This
statement of judicial restraint implies that "policy" is the business of
Congress, at least where the Court does not stake a claim to constitutional
supervision. The Court has not and, in my judgment, will not, with regard to
cloning.
Let me explain, in one more way, why members of Congress are
constrained in this matter by their sworn duty to uphold the Constitution and to
legislate for the common good, unconstrained by judicial doctrine. It is true
that cloning has some features in common with acts that are constitutionally
protected. Cloning is, for example, a way to have a baby, and people (women
especially) have a right to decide whether to have a baby. Also, let us say for
argument sake, that individuals have a right to have babies outside of marriage.
(They do, in the limited sense of being immune to penalties for doing so. But
individuals do not actually have a constitutional right to unwed parenthood.)
Again, you do not have to be married to have baby by cloning.
But, to
observe that cloning is like protected acts in two respects is not saying much.
It is not saying much because cloning posses several additional features, and it
is precisely those additional features which are the grounds of the proposed ban
-- features included in the description of cloning as the asexual manufacture of
genetic replicas. We may presume that members of Congress voting for this bill
do not do so because they are opposed to people having babies, even outside of
wedlock. So far considered, then, members do not adopt as a reason for action
any adverse moral judgment upon any act (or feature of an act) declared by
courts to be private, or none of Congress's business. Congress, in this thought
experiment, regulates only for reasons entirely left open to their policy
judgment by the courts. There is no good reason to anticipate authoritative
judicial action which would block Congressional action upon those reasons. There
is every good reason to conclude that none will be forthcoming.
A
comparison might help to make this point clearer. There is no doubt now that
movies are a constitutionally protected mode of speech. Individuals therefore
may be said to have a right to make movies. And, so long as amenities are
preserved, they have a right to make movies about children, using child actors.
Francis Ford Coppola, for example, may be said to have a right to do a remake of
"Heidi", using the Olson twins as stars. Should Congress attempt to suppress
this project, so far described, Congress would be acted unconstitutionally.
But, does anyone think that if a particular director wished to make a
porno version of "Heidi", using child actresses, he has a right to do so? That
Congress would be acting unconstitutionally by prohibiting child pornography?
Of course not, even though porno "Heidi" possesses, we may suppose,
every feature of Coppola's "Heidi". And that is because porno "Heidi" possesses
one additional feature - sexual exploitation of children - which is not
constitutionally protected.
Cloning possesses many unprotected features.
A Note on IVF
As I noted above, no court in any American
jurisdiction has held in favor of a federal constitutional right to have a child
by in vitro fertilization. It is nevertheless permitted in most, if not all,
jurisdictions. At least one state court (Tennessee), construing its state
constitution, may have implicitly recognized some right to use IVF. Does
approval of IVF imply or suggest approval of cloning? Is a ban on cloning
somehow inconsistent with approval of IVF? Would a projected court decision in
favor of a constitutional right to IVF implicitly undermine the
constitutionality of this bill?
The answer to all these questions is
"No".
IVF and cloning are both methods of asexual human reproduction
which rely upon scientific technique to bring an embryo into being. Both
techniques require the implantation of the embryo into a woman's womb in order
to bring forth a fully developed baby approximately nine months later. But,
otherwise, cloning is radically discontinuous with IVF, and much more distant
from human reproduction as traditionally morally approved, and as recognized in
Due Process cases.
For: the principle of reproduction in IVF procedures
is the human couple. The child born is the issue of two parents, who become
mother and father of that child. That child is genetically unique, the
unrepeatable combination (genetically speaking) of his/her mom and dad. None of
the problems of individuality and identity created by cloning plague IVF. Though
assisted by the lab technician, the embryo is created in IVF as it is within the
woman's body in intercourse: by the spontaneous fusion of gametes -- egg and
sperm. Most important, because of the unique and spontaneous genetic
constitution of the IVF baby, there is scarcely a trace of the manufactured
product status that would be characteristic of cloning.
By contrast,
cloning is the impersonal, individualized undertaking to make a person to the
specifications of a single (genetic) parent. It is replication, not true
reproduction, and it is radically de-humanized. The way to think of IVF in
relation to cloning is an aggravated form of the relation between the two Heidi
movies.
May Congress Ban All
Human Cloning? My
opinion so far has noticed only H.R. 1644, and that insofar as it bans all human
reproductive cloning. But H.R. 1644 goes further, and that further step is what
most distinguishes it from H.R. __ (the Greenwood bill). H.R. 1644 would
prohibit all
human cloning, as the only practical way to make a
ban on reproductive cloning effective. The Greenwood bill would instead ban
cloning "with the intent to initiate a pregnancy". In my opinion, the
comprehensive ban of H.R. 1644 raises no new or interesting constitutional
questions. (1) Also, it is the only practical way to ban reproductive cloning.
The Greenwood bill, by contrast, raises difficult constitutional questions, and
would be wholly ineffective.
Let me explain.
The comprehensive
ban will obviously curtail the activities of researchers who may have no direct
interest in or connection to reproductive cloning. But the judgement that their
activities would imperil the ban on reproductive cloning is entirely for
Congress to make. Since research of the type involved here is a mixture of
speech and act, it is not protected as pure speech is by the Constitution.
Congress has the constitutional power to limit these speech acts in the public
interest. H.R. 1644 does that.
What new constitutional questions does
the Greenwood bill raise? First, by limiting the scope of its prohibition to
some fraction of the comprehensive ban of H.R. 1644, Greenwood necessarily
weakens the Commerce Clause argument in its favor. Recall that the basis for
concluding that H.R. 1644 was on safe interstate commerce ground was the
potentially huge interstate traffic in all types of cloning. By prohibiting one
subset of cloning Greenwood may have to justify itself by reference to imagined
traffic in just that subset. Also, Greenwood does not have the fall-back
interpretation available to H.R. 1644. Nothing in Greenwood suggests that
"affecting interstate commerce" may be an element of each prosecution under it.
By prohibiting only cloning "with the intent to initiate a pregnancy"
Greenwood creates a plausible constitutional argument against itself. It
requires, as a matter of federal law, the intentional destruction of human
embryos, which many consider to be incipient human life. The requirement thus
creates a constituency who will be both opposed to
human
cloning, and to the Greenwood bill (for its required destruction of
embryos). This constituency will be motivated to locate plaintiffs with standing
to save from destruction at least some of those embryos. A nuclear donor,
especially a female nuclear donor asking for "her" embryos in order to have them
implanted in her own womb, has a plausible constitutional argument in favor of a
right to do so.
This female plaintiff will say that, notwithstanding any
contractual agreement with researchers, the fact is that her very tiny child now
exists, and that the courts have two choices. They may authorize the destruction
of her tiny child, or they may restore that tiny child to its mother. She will
rely upon the few decided cases involving frozen embryos, derived from IVF,
cases usually arising out of conflicts engendered by divorce. Those courts have
recognized parental rights in embryos, frozen and in possession of laboratories.
Some of these courts were even willing to put aside contractual agreements for
the destruction of embryos, in light of parental claims to he embryos. In other
words, parents may have the right to change their minds.
Simply put,
allow the creation of embryos by anyone for any purpose, and you create parental
rights. The only way to avoid creating parental rights is to avoid creating
embryos.
The Greenwood ban is not only dubious as a matter of law. It is
untenable and unworkable in practice. Sections 8 (a) and (b) of H.R. 1644
provide sound reasons for concluding that evasions of the Greenwood ban would be
all but undetectable. I should like to add a different set of observations, not
about evading Greenwood, but about the porous quality of its coverage. I shall
speak about human reproductive cloning which is not unlawful under the Greenwood
bill.
Greenwood does not ban the implantation of embryos obtained by
cloning. It does not ban the possession of embryos created by cloning; only
knowing "ship[ping]" and "transport[ing]" the "cellular product" of cloning are
prohibited. Greenwood explicitly immunizes from its reach "other medical
procedures to assist a woman in becoming or remaining pregnant". Simply getting
pregnant with a cloned embryo is entirely outside the scope of this self-styled
"prohibition against
human cloning". In sum, the Greenwood
"prohibition" would actually privilege the creation of an untold number of
embryos suitable for implantation, and does not make any act in connection with
implantation itself unlawful. And a human embryo created for research purposes
is just as suitable for implantation as one created for that end, and vice-
versa..
Now consider this very simple, eminently workable scenario.
The act's main prohibition attaches at the moment of cloning. A
researcher must not clone "with the intent to initiate a pregnancy". A
researcher who undergoes a change of heart could therefore lawfully tell another
person, whom we shall call the "mule", to deliver a vial of embryos (which the
researcher had created days ago in good faith) to an office across town. That
deliverer would not be guilty of "knowingly" shipping or transporting cloning
products. Across town, a doctor takes possession of the embryos, and implants
them in a like number of women. Neither the doctor or the women are guilty of
anything. None created embryos with the intent to cause pregnancy, and none
shipped or transported them at all.
Conclusion
H.R. 1644 makes
good moral sense, is free of constitutional infirmities, and it is practically
enforceable. The Greenwood alternative is morally dubious, constitutionally
questionable, and practically unenforceable.
1. This is probably the
best place to note a shortcoming of draftsmanship in H.R. 1644. It omits all
explicit mention of mens rea. This omission appears to make its provisions
binding in strict liability. Since the ten-year sentence authorized strongly
suggests that either knowing, or perhaps reckless, misconduct is the target of
the bill, some mens rea should be made explicit.
LOAD-DATE: August 8, 2001